Freudian Ethics
No one was more surprised than I was at discovering that a
meta-analysis on the effectiveness of long-term psychodynamic psychotherapy
(LTPP) (psychoanalysis, in other words) published in JAMA last year concluded
that "In this meta-analysis, LTPP was significantly
superior to shorter-term methods of psychotherapy with regard to overall
outcome, target problems, and personality functioning. Long-term psychodynamic
psychotherapy yielded large and stable effect sizes in the treatment of
patients with personality disorders, multiple mental disorders, and chronic
mental disorders. The effect sizes for overall outcome increased significantly
between end of therapy and follow-up." It turns out that statistical
analyses have made an at least plausible case that those years spent in the
"talking cure" are measurably effective, and even more effective than
the more putatively efficient forms of therapy like Cognitive-Behavioral
Therapy. What surprised me most about this study was the surprise that it
engendered in me. "Psychoanalysis is effective as a treatment?" I
thought to myself. "Who knew?" I realize that I had been perfectly
happy handing over the notion of "cure" to other forms of therapy.
For those who simply can't
function in life, even at the normal state of human malaise, "whatever
works" -- cognitive therapy, yoga, medication, exercise -- seems like a
good rule of thumb. Whatever gets you back on your feet, talking to your
friends, making love to your wife, going to work, enjoying the spring. Living
life is, not surprisingly, what makes us able to live life. That thing that
gets us vertical again, into the shower and out into the world, living in a way
that will, if all goes well, become habitual, is what we can call "the
cure." Cures are for illnesses. They are what intervene to stop the
downward spiral, whether it be the spiral to death, to suicide, or to emotional
paralysis and madness.
I have been willing to surrender
the notion of cure in my own thinking on psychoanalysis because I realize that
psychoanalysis, although it was labeled "the talking cure," makes one of its greatest contributions in the very
problematizing of the notion of cure in the first place. As gratified as I am
that psychoanalysis still has a role in curing disorders, it is the same gratification
I feel knowing that having a fun and happy time with my girlfriend has also led
me to lose weight and feel more healthy. A nice side effect, but hardly the key
point.
Now, what I'm saying may be
veering dangerously close to sacrilege. Freud, after all, was a practicing
therapist his whole life. His first models of how the mind functions came out
of the study of people whose physical and emotional sufferings were very real.
But more and more, and building on fairly early insights, Freud became fascinated
with the condition known as normalcy. One of his central insights is that
illness is often an excess of those very mechanisms that we cannot do without
for turning children into fully fledged and functional human beings. In order
to become people who can live with others with a minimum of looting, rape and
murder, we have to go through the wringer of socialization (I will have more to
say in later posts on the Oedipus complex, that most effective of mechanisms
for inducing normalcy). We all have stories of being thwarted, emotionally
amputated, misdirected, punished, cajoled, shamed and conjured into the fine
human specimens we are today. This mutilation of the self is something that
most of us mostly survive. But the normalcy that results is, to say the least,
worthy of a closer look. Freud was, we might argue, the first to really look. What
is truly fascinating for Freud is not how the mechanism breaks down, but how it
works in the first place, not just at the level of the individual, but at the level
of entire societies. What is worth study, after all, are the ways the relative
calm of the human maelstrom is maintained.
This is why the whole notion of
cure misses the mark when we talk about psychoanalysis. What kind of
"cure" acknowledges the indispensability of the disease? Freud did
not offer us psychoanalysis as a cure for the human state, but as an ethical
engagement with that state, and it is as an ethical stance that psychoanalysis
is most important to me.
The ethic of psychoanalysis is as
strange as the human condition that it addresses. The intellectual gesture that
begins psychoanalytic thinking is the acknowledgment and subsequent emptying
out of the banal truth that we are all alike. It is not particularly difficult
to prove that we tend to share impulses and wishes. We all want happiness. We
all bask in the approval of others, we all fear loneliness, pain, rejection. We
all experience our own limits as we run up against the world. What makes us
fascinating and worthy of study is not this commonality of wishes, but the dizzyingly
imaginative and specific defense mechanisms we have each evolved to deal with
these wishes, and the singular product that emerges from the encounter of the
wish and the defense.
The ethic of psychoanalysis is based
in the willingness to value the emergence of what comes into being from this
encounter. It is the ethic of the encounter itself. This is why psychoanalysis
refuses to value the defense alone (it is not an ethic of socialization, of
social control) or the wish alone (it is even less a glorification of the
impulses or pleasures). Nor is it the attempt to reach some soggy compromise
between the two. The "compromise" that Freud speaks of in the
encounter of the wish and the resistance is only a compromise in the same sense
that a boxing match is a compromise: it involves two principals who need each
other, it requires a clash that unfolds in time and in a structured
environment, it requires that one fighter win while the other lives to fight
another day. Each fight is -- like any individual -- known by its proper name: Ali-Foreman,
Hagler-Hearns, Gatti-Ward. The fight is as much an individual as it is an
event, and the person as much an event as an individual.
Psychoanalytic ethics begins with
this recognition of the individual as event, the event of the coming together
of the wish and the resistance. To be true to this event (as Alain Badiou might
put it) requires an ongoing openness to its emergences and reemergences. It
also requires that subjectivity function from outside of any location. Neither
in the wish, nor in the resistance, subjectivity is what emerges again and
again. Not a foundation, not a guarantee of reason and rationality, not a
domesticated space, subjectivity is a kind of continual birth, appearance,
flash, shimmer of the event.
How can such moments of the human
adventure ever be captured by the notion of "cure." We cannot be
cured of the radical split in our being, of our attachment to our fantasies, of
that unknown and uncanny space of the unconscious from which the embryo of our
lives comes. There is, in short, no cure for coming into a world where all
space and all time are not ours, where we are entangled in the desires of
others, living and dead, where the unknown is the parent of the known. In such
a world, what most increases our power to act and to know is not a cure, but an
ethics, a way to shape the event of the self as it flows through our hands. If
psychoanalysis can also break the paralysis of excessive suffering, so much the
better, but the power by which it can cure illness is, I would argue, just an
offshoot of the power by which stakes its claim to truth: the power to never
stop welcoming the next emergence of whatever event is to come.
Comments
Post a Comment